Al-Nayrīz

views updated

AL-NAYRīZī, ABU’L-‘ABBāS AL-FAḌL IBN ḤāTIM

(fl. Baghdad, ca. 897; d. ca. 922)

geometry, astronomy.

As his name indicates, al-Nayrīzī’s origins were in Nayrīz, a small town southeast of Shīrāz, Fārs, Iran. For at least part of his active life he lived in Baghdad, where he probably served the ‘Abbāsid caliph al-Mu‘tadid (892–902), for whom he wrote an extant treatise on meteorological phenomena (Risāla fī ahdāth al-jaww) and a surviving work on instruments for determining the distances of objects.

The tenth-century bibliographer Ibn al-Nadīm refers to al-Nayrīzī as a distinguished astronomer; Ibn al-Qif̣tī (d. 1248) states that he excelled in geometry and astronomy; and the Egyptian astronomer Ibn Yūnus (d. 1009) takes exception to some of al-Nayrīzī’s astronomical views but shows respect for him as an accomplished geometer.

Of the eight titles attributed to al-Nayrīzī by Ibn al-Nadīm and Ibn al-Qif̣tī, two are commentaries on Ptolemy’s Almagest and Tetrabiblos and two are astronomical handbooks (zijes). Ibn al-Qif̣tī indicates that the larger handbook (Kitāb al-zīj al-kabīr) was based on the Sindhind. None of these works has survived, but the commentary on the Almagest and one (or both?) of the handbooks were known to al-Bīrūnī. Ibn Yūnus cites, critically, a certain zīj in which, he states, al-Nayrīzī adopted the mean motion of the sun as determined in the Mumtahan zīj, which was prepared under the direction of Yahyā ibn Abī Maṇsūr in the time of al-Ma’mun (813–833). Ibn Yūnus wonders at al-Nayrīzī;s adoption of this “erroneous” determination without further examination and, continuing his criticism of the “excellent geometer,” refers further to oversights and errors, particularly in connection with the theory of Mercury, the eclipse of the moon, and parallax.

AI-Nayrīzī has been known mainly as the author of a commentary on Euclid’s Elements that was based on the second of two Arabic translations of Euclid’s text, both of which were prepared by al-Hajjāj ibn Yūsuf ibn Matar (see Dictionary of Scientific Biography, IV, 438–439). The commentary survives in a unique Arabic manuscript at Leiden (bks. I-VI) and in a Latin version (bks. I-X), made in the twelfth century by Gerard of Cremona. (The Arabic manuscript lacks the comments on definitions 1–23 of book I, but these are preserved in the Latin translation.) In the course of his own comments al-Nayrīzī quotes extensively from two commentaries on the Elements by Hero of Alexandria and Simplicius, neither of which has survived in the original Greek.

The first of these must have covered at least the first eight books (Hero’s last comment cited by al-Nayrīzī deals with Euclid VIII.27), whereas the second, entitled “A Commentary on the Premises [̣sadr, muṣādara, muṣādarāt] of Euclid’s Elements,” was concerned solely with the definitions, postulates, and axioms at the beginning of hook I of the Elements.

Simplicius’ Commentary, almost entirely reproduced by al-Nayrīzī, played a significant part in arousing the interest of Islamic mathematicians in methodological problems. It further quotes verbatim a full proof of Euclid’s postulate 5, the parallels postulate, by “the philosopher Aghānīs.” The proof, which is based on the definition of parallel lines as equidistant lines and which makes use of the “Eudoxus-Archimedes” axiom, has left its mark on many subsequent attempts to prove the postulate, particularly in Islam.

Aghānīs is no longer identified with Geminus, as Heiberg and others once thought because of a similarity between their views on parallels. He almost certainly lived in the same period as Simplicius; and Simplicius’ reference to him in the Commentary as “our associate [or colleague] Aghānīs,” or, simply,“our Aghānīs” (Aghānīsu, sāhibunā, rendered by Gerard as socius noster Aganis) strongly suggests that the two philosophers belonged to the same school. There is an anonymous fifteenth-century Arabic manuscript that aims to prove Euclid’s parallels postulate and refers in this connection to Simplicius and Aghānīs, but spells the latter’s name “Aghānyūs,” thus supplying a vowel that can only be conjectured in the form “Aghānīs.” Given that the Arabic “gh” undoubtedly stood for the letter λ, “Aghānyūs” may very easily have been a mistranscription of the recognizable Greek name “Agapius.” Reading “Aghānyūs” for “Aghābyūs” (Arabic has no “p”) may well have resulted from misplacing a single diacritical point, thereby transforming the “b” (that is, “p”) into an “n.” This hypothesis is the more plausible since we know that diacritical points were often omitted in Arabic manuscripts. it therefore seems reasonable to assume that Aghānīs-Aghānyūs was no other than the Athenian philosopher Agapius, a pupil of Proclus and Marinus who lectured on the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle about a.d. 511 and whose versatility was praised by Simplicius’ teacher, Damascius. Agapius’ name, place, date, affiliation, and interests agree remarkably with the reference in Simplicius’ Commentary.

In his commentary on the Elements, al-Nayrīzī followed a conception of ratio and proportion that had previously been adopted by al-Māhāni (see Dictionary of Scientific Biography, IX, 21–22). Al-Nayrīzī’s treatise “On the Direction of the qibla” (Risāla fi samt al-qibla) shows that he knew and utilized the equivalent of the tangent function. But in this, too, he is now known to have been preceded, for example, by Habash (see Dictionary of Scientific Biography, V, 612).

Again, his unpublished treatise “On the Demonstration of the Well-Known Postulate of Euclid” (Paris, Bibliothèque Nationale, arabe 2467, fols. 89r–90r) clearly depends on Aghānīs. In it al-Nayrīzī argues that, because equality is “naturally prior” to inequality, it follows that straight lines that maintain the same distance between them are prior to those that do not, since the former are the standard for estimating the latter. From this reasoning he concludes the existence of equidistant lines, accepting as a “primary proposition” that equidistant lines do not meet, however extended. His proof consists of four propositions, of which the first three state that: (1) the distance (that is, shortest line) between any two equidistant lines is perpendicular to both lines; (2) if a straight line drawn across two straight lines is perpendicular to both of them, then the two lines are equidistant; and (3) a line falling on two equidistant lines makes the interior angles on one side together equal to two right angles. These three propositions correspond to Aghānīs’s propositions 1–3, while the fourth is the same as Euclid’s postulate 5: If a straight line falling on two straight lines makes the interior angles on one side together less than two right angles, then the two lines will meet on that side. The proof closely follows Aghānīs.

Al-Nayrīzī, however, claims originality for the theorems that he proves in the extant but unpublished treatise for al-Mu‘tadid—“On the Knowledge of Instruments by Means of Which We May Know the Distances of Objects Raised in the Air or Set Up on the Ground and the Depths of Valleys and Wells, and the Widths of Rivers.” Al-Bīrūnī also states that al-Nayrīzī, in his commentary on the Almagest, was the only writer known to him who had provided a method for computing “a date for a certain time, the known parts of which are various species that do not belong to one and the same genus. There is, e.g., a day the date of which within a Greek, Arabic, or Persian month is known; but the name of this month is unknown, whilst you know the name of another month that corresponds with it. Further, you know an era, to which, however, these two months do not belong, or such an era, of which the name of the month in question is not known” (Chronology, p. 139).

Al-Nayrīzī’s work on the construction and use of the spherical astrolabe (Fi’l-asturlāb al-kurī), in four maqālas, is considered the most complete treatment of the subject in Arabic.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

I. Original Works. The Arabic text of al-Nayrīzī’s commentary on the Elements (bks. I-VI and a few lines from bk. VII) was published as Codex Leidensis 399, I. Euclidis Elemcnta ex interpretatione al-Hadschdschadschii cum commentariis al-Narizii, R. O. Besthorn and J. L. Heiberg, eds. (Copenhagen, 1893–1932). This ed. is in three pts., each comprising two fascicules, of which pt. III, fasc. II (bks. V-VI), is edited by G. Junge, J. Raeder and W. Thomson. Gerard of Cremona’s Latin trans, is Anaritii in decem libros priores Elementorum Euclidis commentarii… in codice Cracoviensi 569 servata, Maximilianus Curtze, cd. (Leipzig, 1899), in Euclid’s Opera omnia, J. L. Heiberg and H. Menge, eds., supp. (Suter mentions the probable existence of another MS of Gerard’s trans, in “Nachträge,” p. 164).

A German trans, and discussion of ai-Nayrīzī’s treatise on the direction of the qibla (Risāla fi samt al-qibla) is C. Schoy, “Abhandlung von al-Fadl b. Hâtim an Nairîzî: Ober die Rechtung der Qibla,” in Sitzungsbcrichte der koniglichen baierischen Akademte der Wissenschaften zu Miinchen, Mathematisch-physikalische Klasse (1922), 55–68.

A short “chapter” (perhaps drawn from a longer work by al Nayrizi) on the hemispherical sundial was published as Fasl fi takhtīt al-sd’at al-zamdniyya fi kull qubba aw fi qubba tusta’mal laha (“On Drawing the Lines of Temporal [that is, unequal] Hours in Any Hemisphere or in a Hemisphere Used for That Purpose”);see al-Rasā’il al-mutafarriqa fi hay’a I ‘l-mutaqaddimin wa-mifasiri ‘l-Bimni (Hyderabad, 1947).

II. Secondary Literature. MSS of al-Nayrīzī’s works are in C. Brockelmann, Geschichte der arabischen Literalur, supp. vol. I (Leiden, 1937), 386–387; 2nd ed., I, (Leiden, 1943), 245; H. Suter, “Die Mathematiker und Astronomen der Araber und ihre Werke,” in Abhandltungen zur Geschichte der mathematischen Wissenschaften mit Einschluss ihrer Amvendungen, 10 (1900), no. 88, 45; and “Nachtrage und Berichtigungen zu ‘Die Mathematiker …,’” ibid., 14 (1902), 164; and H. P. J. Rcnaud, “Additions et corrections a Suter ‘Die Mathematiker…” in Isis, 18 (1932), 171.

The little information that we have of al-Nayrīzī’s activities and a list of his works are in Ibn al-Nadīm, al-Fihrist, G. Fliigel, ed., 1 (Leipzig, 1871), 265, 268, 279; and lbn al-Qif̣tī, Ta’rīkh al-hukamā, J. Lippen, ed. (Leipzig, 1930), 64, 97, 98, 254.

For the references to al-Nayrīzī’s zīj in Ibn Yūnus’ Hākimite zīj, see Notices et extraits des manuscrits de la Bibliothèque nationale…, VII (Paris, 1803), 61, 65, 69, 71, 73, 121, 161, 165. Al-Bīrūnī refers to al-Nayrīzī in Rasā’il, 2 (Hyderabad, 1948), 39, 51, and in The Chronology of Ancient Nations, C. E. Sachau, trans. (London, 1879), 139. See also E. S. Kennedy, “A Survey of Islamic Astronomical Tables,” in Transactions of the American Philosophical Society, n, s. 46, pt. 2 (1956), nos. 46 , 63, 75.

For a description of the contents and character of Hero’s commentary on the Elements as preserved by al-Nayrīzī, see T. L. Heath, The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements, 2nd ed. (Cambridge-New York, 1956), 21–24.

Simplicius’ commentary on the Elements, including a proof of Euclid’s parallels postulate that seems to have been omitted from the text quoted by al-Nayrīzī, is discussed by A. I. Sabra in “Simplicius’s Proof of Euclid’s Parallels Postulate,” in Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, 32 (1969), 1–24.

For a detailed description of al-Nayrīzī’s work on the spherical astrolabe, see Hugo Seemann and T. Mittelberger, “Das kugelförmige Astrolab nach den Mitteilungen von Alfonso X. von Kastilien und den vorhandenen arabischen Quellen,” in Abhandhmgen zur Geschichte der N’atur-wissenschaften und der Medizin, 8 (1925), 32–40.

For a discussion of al-Nayrīzī’s concept of ratio, see E. B. Plooij, Euclid’s Conception of Ratio and His Definition of Proportional Magnitudes as Criticized by Arabian Commentators (Rotterdam, 1950), 51–52, 61; and J. E. Murdoch, “The Medieval Language of Proportions,” in A. C. Crombie, ed., Scientific Change (London, 1963), 237–271, esp. 240–242, 253–255.

The identity of Aghānīs is discussed in Paul Tannery, “Le philosophe Aganis est-il identique à Géminus?” in i, 3rd ser., 2 (1901), 9–11, reprinted in Memoires scientifiques, III (Toulouse-Paris, 1915), 37–41; Sir Thomas Heath, A History of Greek Mathematics, II (Oxford, 1921), 224; The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements, I (Cambridge-New York, 1956), 27–28; A. I. Sabra, “Thabit ibn Qurra on Euclid’s Parallels Postulate,” in Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, 31 (1968), 13. The information on Agapius is summarized in Pauly-Wissowa, Real-Encyclopddie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft, 1st ser., I (Stuttgart, 1894), 735.

See also the notice on al-Nayrīzī in Sarton’s Introduction, I (Baltimore, 1927), 598–599.

A. I. Sabra

More From encyclopedia.com

About this article

Al-Nayrīz

Updated About encyclopedia.com content Print Article

You Might Also Like

    NEARBY TERMS

    Al-Nayrīz