Social and Political Elites

views updated

SOCIAL AND POLITICAL ELITES

At one level, elites can be defined simply as persons who hold dominant positions in major institutions or are recognized leaders in art, education, business, and other fields of achievement. Such individuals exist in all societies, but beyond this mundane observation, social scientists are interested in why particular individuals attain positions of status and power. Does achievement reflect superior talent, or is it a product of social or cultural advantage? Why are some achievements valued over others? How does the distribution of elite positions in society reflect the particular social structures in which they exist? These questions are the focus of much research on stratification and social inequality.

In the social sciences, the concept of elites refers to a more specific issue as well: the concentration of societal power—especially political power—in the hands of a few. At the heart of theoretical debates and empirical research on elites is the famous assertion of Mosca (1939, p. 50): "In all societies . . . two classes of people appear—a class that rules and a class that is ruled." One can distinguish the conception of "functional elites" in a variety of institutional contexts from that of a "ruling" or "political" elite that in some sense wields societal-level power. Then the key questions concern the existence and nature of this dominant group. Is power over the major institutions of society highly concentrated, or is it broadly dispersed as "pluralists" claim? If a cohesive ruling elite exists, then who is in it and what is the basis of its power? What is the extent of its power in relation to the nonelite "masses"? Does this societal elite exercise power responsibly in the interests of society as a whole, or do elites maximize their own interests against those of subordinate groups?


CLASSICAL ELITE THEORY

Social thought on elites goes back at least to Plato and Aristotle, but contemporary debates usually begin with the "neo-Machiavellians" Pareto (1935), Mosca (1939), and Michels ([1915] 1959). Reacting to the turmoil of European society in the early twentieth century, each developed arguments supporting the inevitability of elite rule in opposition to classical democratic theory, Marxian class analysis, and socialist political movements. For Pareto, elites in general were those holding leadership positions in business, politics, education, and other areas of accomplishment. Those individuals could be distinguished from the rest of "nonelite" society. He further distinguished between the "governing elite"—the segment of the elite with broad political power—and the nongoverning elite. His best known statements concerned the former group. Though famous for his work in mathematical economics, Pareto believed that most human behavior was nonrational, the expression of deep-seated "sentiments" and their observable manifestations, or "residues." These motivational orientations led to behaviors that were then "explained" through our post hoc rationalizations, or "derivations" (1935, chap. IX). For Pareto, the governing elites were those with dominant talents or leadership skills derived primarily from superior individual attributes. Borrowing from Machiavelli, he distinguished two ideal types of political leaders on the basis of their dominant personal qualities and motivations ("residues"). "Lions" appealed to the conservative instincts that were most common in the masses, relying on tradition, strength, and coercion to rule. "Foxes" were more innovative leaders who relied on cunning, new ideas, and manipulation. Both types were necessary, but Pareto tended to see a cyclical pattern of rule in societies in which "foxes" dominated in periods of upheaval and transition, only to be displaced by "lions" after the restoration of social order (1935, chap. XII).

Pareto also noted that individuals in positions of power often attempt to maintain their privileged positions by closing off access for others. This risks social disruption by shutting off avenues of achievement and power to other talented individuals, who then mobilize to affect change. The "circulation of elites" refers to the process by which the ruling class is renewed periodically by superior individuals from other ranks. For Pareto, obstacles to elite circulation often resulted in the stagnation of the ruling class. Closed aristocracies and caste-like systems fostered tension, conflict, and eventually social change.

Like Pareto, Mosca began with the assertion that elite rule is an empirical fact in all societies. Although he also noted the superior individual attributes of the "ruling class," his analysis was considerably more sociological than that of Pareto. Mosca emphasized the organizational advantages of the ruling elite in that they represented a relatively cohesive and easily organized minority against the disorganized masses (Mosca 1939, p. 53). He also discussed the role of the "subelite," a technocratic stratum of managers, intellectuals, and bureaucrats that was increasingly important for elite rule in modern societies (1939, pp. 404–409; see also Marger 1987, p. 54). Mosca's conception of social change and the circulation of elites was also more sociological. Social, economic, and technological changes often generated new opportunities and called forth new talents, bringing new elites into prominence. Mosca agreed with Pareto that closed systems of rule threatened social stability, since a stagnant elite impeded adaptation to change.

In Political Parties ([1915] 1959), Michels traced the necessity of elite rule in modern societies to the imperatives of complex organization. His classic study analyzed the German Social Democratic Party, but his arguments have been applied to a variety of organizational contexts. Influenced by Weber's ([1921] 1968) work on politics and bureaucracy, Michels's most famous conclusion is summarized in his "Iron Law of Oligarchy," the argument that large-scale organizations necessarily concentrate power in the hands of a few at the top. Once in power, leaders in organizations such as labor unions and political parties act to preserve their positions. Those who rise from lower levels in the organization are co-opted in a process that preserves the structure of power. The resources available to institutional leaders and their relative unity of interest and perspective give them numerous advantages in maintaining their power over the unorganized rank and file. Over time, leaders develop similar interests and intraelite attachments that reflect their elevated position and separate them from the masses. For their part, Michels saw the masses contributing to elite rule through their general apathy and acquiescence. With his focus on organizational factors, Michels has been very influential in the development of contemporary elite approaches to power (see Marger 1987, pp. 56–58; Burton and Higley 1987).


C. WRIGHT MILLS AND THE ELITE-PLURALIST DEBATE

Among elite theorists there is an important distinction between those who see the concentration of power as inevitable or desirable and those who do not. The former group includes the classical elite theorists and those who have extended their ideas (see Field and Higley 1980; Burton and Higley 1987). In contrast, "critical" or "radical" elite theorists recognize the concentration of power in society but argue that this condition is neither inevitable nor desirable. Unlike the classical theorists who emphasized mass apathy or incompetence, critical elite theorists argue that elite domination is maintained through the manipulation and exploitation of nonelites.

The most influential representative of the critical elite perspective is Mills (1956). Mills, Hunter (1953), and other critical elite theorists developed their work in response to the dominance of "pluralist" studies of political power in the United States. Pluralism, as represented in the work of Dahl (1956), Truman (1951), Riesman (1950), and others, held that power in modern democratic societies was widely dispersed and that those in decision-making positions were subject to significant mass pressures (through electoral or other processes) or the countervailing power of other institutional elites or organized interest groups. For Mills, the notion of a pluralist balance of power between competing interest groups was a romantic ideal rather than a description of political reality in the United States. He acknowledged the activities of labor unions, farm groups, professional associations, and other organized interest groups but argued that those groups operated mainly at the secondary, local, and "middle levels" of power. The power to make decisions of national and international scope rested with a "power elite" of individuals in top positions of authority in major corporations, the executive branch of government, and the military. Congress was consigned to the middle levels of power, along with most of the interest groups studied by pluralist social scientists. Mills traced the historical consolidation of the power elite to the growth of the federal government in the 1930s and especially during World War II, as industrial production was coordinated with military needs through the government. That institutional alignment was strengthened in the Cold War years as the state expanded its commitment to national security, social welfare, and the direction of economic policy. By the 1950s there was a significant shift in power from Congress to the executive branch, reflecting an expansion of government that required a complex information-gathering and administrative capacity. Congress lacked the resources and coherence required for modern state administration.

Mills argued that most of the members of the power elite had similar values and interests, which reflected their similar backgrounds, common schools, shared membership in elite social clubs, and informal social interaction. He also emphasized the continuous professional interaction between these institutional leaders and the frequent exchange of top personnel between major corporations, the military, and the executive branch of government. Another factor contributing to the relative homogeneity of the power elite was their common experience at the apex of bureaucratic institutions. The skills, status, and even personality type required for success were similar in each sphere, reflecting their similarity of organizational structure (Mills 1956, p. 15).

The other side of Mills's conception of the power elite was that of mass society. The same social processes that had concentrated political power had created a society of increasingly fragmented individuals whose lives and interests were shaped for them from above. Information filtered selectively through bureaucratized institutions of mass education and the mass media, which became more susceptible to elite manipulation as they became more centralized. The media emphasized entertainment and consumption over information and critique. Educational institutions had developed into sites of large-scale vocational training rather than havens for the development of critical thought and an informed citizenry necessary for democratic politics (Mills 1956, chap. 13).

Mills's work became the touchstone for debates about the structure of power in the United States that have continued to this day. Pluralists argue that he exaggerated the unity of functional elites and neglected the influence of the electoral process and interest group competition. From the other direction, neo-Marxist and other class-theoretical analysts have been critical of the Millsian model for not acknowledging the extent to which political power is shaped by dominant economic interests (see the debates collected in Domhoff and Ballard 1968). A key question in these disputes concerns the degree of elite cohesion. How much consensus (or competition) between elites is required to support an elite (or pluralist) model? What is the extent of elite competition? Is there a hierarchy of elites, with a ruling class or "power elite" on top, or a "polyarchy" (Dahl 1971) of diverse institutional powers? Elite theorists acknowledge that individuals with different skills and constituencies hold leadership positions in a variety of institutions such as prestigious universities, private foundations, major civic organizations, and the media (see Dye 1995). Pluralists view these institutions as relatively autonomous sources of societal influence. Although one may identify "strategic elites," or influential leaders, in a variety of fields (Keller 1963), they see no overall cohesion or uniform coordination of policy within a single ruling group. However, those defending an elite perspective argue that disagreements over particular interests occur within a general elite consensus on basic ideology and acceptable policy. Developing Mills's arguments, elite theorists have studied avariety of coordinating mechanisms that foster elite cohesion, such as private school ties, social networks, shared membership in policy planning organizations, and the general recruitment process in which future leaders are instilled with attitudes conducive to maintaining the existing structure of power (see Prewitt and Stone 1973; Marger 1987; Bottomore 1993; Dye 1995; Domhoff 1998). Some who work in this tradition go further than Mills in emphasizing the prominence of class interests and corporate power over the political process and other institutions in capitalist societies (Miliband 1969; Useem 1983; Domhoff 1990, 1998). Indeed, the distinction between "elite" and "class "analysis disappears in many such works (on the similarities and differences, see Marger 1987). From this perspective, prestigious Ivy League universities may harbor intellectuals critical of the existing power structure, that but only those academics with "acceptable" views are selected as advisers to political elites in turn must maintain acceptable levels of business confidence and campaign finance to remain in power.

In a similar vein, all parties agree that in a modern democratic system, the "elite," however defined, must pay some attention to the "masses." The question is, How much attention must be paid, and how do public preferences impose themselves on elites? Pluralists hold that the public has a significant influence on elite decision making through voting, public opinion, and the threat of social protest. From a different starting point, some class-based analysts note the role of working class mobilization or the effects of other nonelite social movements, such as the civil rights movement, that force changes in the polity and society (Piven and Cloward 1977). By contrast, those who emphasize elite power tend to leave little room for the influence of nonelites in promoting major social change. Change is viewed as the result of elite mobilization, intraelite conflict, or the circulation of elites. Mills, for example, viewed the major societal decisions in the United States as the product of elite decision making, while more specific, localized issues were more likely to be negotiated at the "middle levels" of power. Domhoff (1998) considers major policy formation processes by looking at the "agenda-setting" power of elites, noting that while pluralistic interest group competition does occur on specific issues, the general parameters of public discourse and public policy are set in advance and behind the scenes through organizations such as policy planning groups and presidential task forces that bring elites together to build a consensus on major policy issues before specific proposals enter the formal legislative process. Other elite theorists point out that even in periods of mass mobilization over policy issues, the power of elites over the public agenda allows public sentiment to be deflected or diffused by temporary measures or by redirecting public attention to peripheral issues (Prewitt and Stone 1973, pp. 107–108).


MODERNIZATION, MERITOCRACY, AND ELITE RECRUITMENT

The dominant view of elites in the 1950s developed out of the structural functionalism of Parsons (1940; 1951) and the "end-of-ideology" arguments that appeared around that time (see Waxman 1968). This perspective, which is popular again today, holds that with the emergence of modern industrial societies and liberal democracy, elites increasingly represent a stratum of talented individuals filling important positions of leadership in dominant institutions (see especially Keller 1963; see also Mannheim 1940; Aron 1950). Variations on this theme point to a "New Class" of "knowledge" workers in "postindustrial" managerial and information-based professions and a proliferation of new institutional elites that transcend the old hierarchies of caste and class (Keller 1963; Bell 1974). From this perspective, modern elites are functionally necessary in a society of complex organizations and increasingly specialized occupations. Echoing Davis and Moore's (1945) functionalist theory of stratification, status and material rewards are seen to reflect the high skill and social responsibility required for those positions. The legitimacy of functional elites is supported to the extent that relatively equal opportunities to attain those positions are available to all talented and motivated individuals.

The validity of this "meritocracy" model of power is directly related to the issue of elite recruitment and the extent to which positions of power are open to nonelites. Once again, at one level there is general agreement among all parties on the relative openness of modern societies in comparison to traditional systems in which elite "recruitment" often was based on birth. In contemporary societies, differentiation fostered a proliferation of institutional elites requiring specific talents and skills in a variety of fields (see Keller 1963). However, beyond this empirical fact, the questions of contention are: (1) How much openness is there? and (2) Does it matter?

The first question has been the subject of much research in stratification and will be dealt with only briefly here. The meritocracy model assumes equal opportunity for individuals, but considerable research has challenged this assumption. For example, if elite positions are based on merit, educational institutions must provide avenues for mobility and equal opportunity for talented individuals from nonelite backgrounds, but a basic criticism of functionalist theories of stratification is that existing structures of inequality create barriers to nonelite achievement (see Tumin 1953). Beyond the obvious inequality of economic resources and formal educational institutions, the work of Bourdieu and others (Bourdieu 1984; Bourdieu and Passeron 1977; DiMaggio and Mohr 1985) has shown how the unequal distribution of "cultural capital" among groups in different locations in the class structure contributes to the reproduction of inequality in a variety of subtle ways. This research also points to the difficulty in assessing differences in "talent" among individuals or groups, since indicators such as "intelligence," cultural appreciation, and political knowledge may reflect a preexisting distribution of cultural resources.

A more fundamental question regarding the openness of elite recruitment is: Does it matter? First, if the concern is the overall structure of power, as it was for Mills and most elite theorists, the success of a few upwardly mobile individuals from the lower strata does not affect the analysis: Power still may be concentrated in a few in key positions. Second, elite recruitment from the lower ranks does not necessarily affect the content of elite decision making, given the selection process involved in the rise of "talented" individuals into elite positions. Most analysts agree that in modern societies, attainment of elite positions often requires a degree of talent, effort, and achievement, but elite theorists argue that those who make it to the top are selected for specific orientations that are compatible with existing structures of power. Those from privileged backgrounds, with access to economic, social, or cultural capital, have a definite advantage, but it is possible for nonelites people who possess the right attitudes and skills to rise into positions of power. This maintains the existing structure of power while providing legitimating examples of individual success. Limited avenues for mobility also provide a mechanism for the co-optation of promising leaders from below, as Pareto and Mosca would recognize (see the discussions of elite recruitment in Prewitt and Stone 1973; Marger 1987; Bottomore 1993; Dye 1995; Domhoff 1998).


ELITES AND DEMOCRACY

There have been a number of modifications of both "elite" and "pluralist" theory that have brought the two closer together. The work of Weber, Michels, and others influenced later theorists who viewed the concentration of power in modern institutions as necessary. From this vantage point, the issue was not whether broad "democratic" participation in political, economic, and other institutions was possible (it was not) but whether the interests of nonelites could be preserved in the face of modern bureaucratic organization. Democratic elitism represented a refinement of pluralist assumptions that redefined democracy in a manner congruent with elite rule. Given the inevitable concentration of power in modern societies, the central problem became: What legitimates elite rule or preserves elite "accountability"? The traditional answer of conservative elitists had been the "virtue," "character," or inward convictions of elite leaders in comparison to the selfish and undisciplined masses. In this tradition, with adherents from Plato to Pareto, elites have a stronger commitment to the "public interest" than do the "people" (Prewitt and Stone 1973, pp. 188–196). The meritocracy model represents a contemporary variation of this viewpoint: Modern institutions require skilled leadership, and this means that institutional elites are increasingly likely to be selected on the basis of superior talent.

Another source of public accountability important for "democratic elitists" is elite competition for electoral support. Political elites must compete for votes in formal democracies, and this acts as a broad restraint on their actions. However, once in office, elite decision makers are relatively free to act as they see fit as long as their actions remain within acceptable limits. In a well-known formulation by Schumpeter (1942), elite rule is preserved both by superior talent and by the general mass apathy that he saw as functional for political rule. For Schumpeter (1942, pp. 269–296) and other conservative advocates of democratic elitism, the efficiency of modern representative governments depends on the "people" selecting their leaders and then leaving them alone. Note that the definition of "democracy" has been transformed from an emphasis on maximum public participation in political life to an assertion of the functional necessity of nonparticipation. Far from government "by the people," democracy is now defined as a procedure for the selection of political elites. This underscores the difficulty in weighing empirical claims concerning "democratic" representation made by competing theories, given the radically divergent definitions of the key concept. Classical theories of democracy emphasized the importance of political participation as an end in itself, one that was necessary for the creation of political citizens capable of democratic self-rule (Pateman 1970). Critics of conservative elitism such as Bottomore (1993, p. 95) wonder if "a person can live in a condition of complete and unalterable subordination for much of the time, and yet acquire the habits of responsible choice and self government which political democracy calls for." This issue is muddier for the fact that many critical elite theorists are ambivalent about the possibilities for participatory democracy in modern society. If elite rule is undesirable, it would seem necessary to provide an alternative. Mills held up participatory democracy as an ideal from which to judge the contemporary United States in his concept of "publics" (1956, pp. 302– 304), but he was not very clear about how that ideal could be implemented in modern "mass society." Other critical elite theorists seem to have accepted the classical argument for the inevitability of elite rule in modern, bureaucratically organized socities (see Prewitt and Stone 1973; Marger 1987; Burton and Higley 1987). For these critics, the only option to a "democracy" of mass apathy is one in which political institutions and decision-making elites are as open as possible to public scrutiny by a truly informed electorate.


LIMITATIONS OF THE ELITE PARADIGM

The elite paradigm—and by extension the "elitismpluralism" debate as it usually is formulated—focuses on the leaders of large-scale organizations and organized institutions. Power is based on command over organizational resources; the elites are those in positions of organized power. While there are other ways to conceptualize elites, this is the dominant model in the social sciences today (see Marger 1987; Burton and Higley 1987; Dye 1995). Most scholars agree that power is concentrated in such organizations. The disagreements occur over whether there is a unified "ruling elite" above and beyond these multiple institutional elites that characterize all modern societies.

This controversy has led to much fruitful research and theoretical debate, but the "elitistpluralist" framework is less adequate for dealing with other dimensions of societal power. For example, many of the social and cultural processes involved in the reproduction of class, gender, and racial inequality cannot be encompassed within an organizational paradigm. This includes socialization processes and everyday practices within the family, school, and workplace that reproduce the hegemony of a dominant culture. Further, it is possible to map the formal leadership structure of educational institutions, research foundations, and media organizations without explaining the content of their decisions. One might ask: Elite power, yes, but power for what? With its emphasis on the power of individuals within organizations, the elite paradigm neglects many structural and cultural forces that constrain those organizations and the elites within them. For example, how do global economic conditions and the imperative of "business confidence" constrain the decisions of political and economic elites? How are the ideologies and cultural practices that govern gender relations reproduced in the boardroom or the executive mansion? These questions are significant, because without them it is difficult to explain why elites make the decisions they do or why some societal interests are better represented than others are in the decision-making process. It is necessary to consider elites and the organizations they command in their larger social and cultural context.

This issue was highlighted many years ago in debates over the "managerial revolution thesis." This was an argument that modern corporations are different from traditional capitalist enterprises because of their separation of ownership from management. Managers were seen to have aims different from those of capitalists, reflecting their organizational position. They were more interested in long-term growth, stability, labor peace, and good community relations—good management—and less concerned with profit maximization (Berle and Means 1932; Burnham 1941) The simple but fundamental weakness in such an argument was that managers—the "elites" who wield organizational power in modern corporations—were still constrained by the imperatives of the market and capital accumulation. Time has shown that their ability to act "managerially" reflected a brief postwar period of U.S. dominance in the world economy. Global competition has since required that corporate elites act more like representatives of capital.

The same might be said about political elites as well, which brings one back to the issue of the relationship between political power and class interest. Recent debates in political sociology over the degree to which state institutions, governing officials, and policy intellectuals are "relatively autonomous" from the constraints of class interest or other societal pressures have again brought into focus the relationship between political power and economic interest (see Skocpol 1985; Jessop 1990). Class theorists have argued that the decisions of political elites are shaped not only by the superior resources of a dominant class but also by the structural constraints on the state in a market economy (see Block 1977; Lindbloom 1977). Others have traced a clear class bias and pro-capital selectivity inherent in the very institutions of modern states and the dominant political discourse ( Jessop 1990). Parallel arguments have been made by feminists who hold that patriarchal domination is embedded in the very structure of the state (e.g., MacKinnon 1989). These lines of inquiry do not negate the importance of research on elites, but they lead one to ask questions about the larger social forces that shape their decisions.


references

Aron, Raymond 1950 "Social Structrure and the Ruling Class." British Journal of Sociology 1:126–144.

Bell, Daniel 1974 The Coming of Post-Industrial Society. New York: Basic Books.

Berle, A. A., and G. C. Means 1932 The Modern Corporation and Private Property. New York: Macmillan.

Block, Fred 1977 "The Ruling Class Does Not Rule." Socialist Revolution 7(3):6–28.

Bottomore Tom 1993. Elites and Society. London: Routledge.

Bourdieu, Pierre 1984 Distinction: A Social Critique of theJudgment of Taste. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

——, and J. C. Passeron 1977 Reproduction in Education, Society, and Culture. Beverley Hills, Calif.: Sage.

Burnham, James 1941 The Managerial Revolution. New York: Day.

Burton, Michael G., and John Higley 1987 "Invitation to Elite Theory." In G. William Domhoff and Thomas Dye, eds., Power Elites and Organizations. Newbury Park, Calif: Sage Publications pp. 219–238.

Dahl, Robert A. 1956 A Preface to Democratic Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

—— 1971 Polyarchy. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.

Davis, Kingsley, and Wilbert Moore, 1945 "Some Principles of Stratification." American Sociological Review 10(2): 242–249.

DiMaggio, Paul, and John Mohr 1985 "Cultural Capital, Educational Attainment, and Marital Selection." American Journal of Sociology 90: 1231–1261.

Domhoff, G. William 1990 The Power Elite and the State. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.

—— 1998 Who Rules America? Power and Politics in theYear 2000. Mountain View, Calif.: Mayfield.

—— and Hoyt B. Ballard, eds. 1968 C. Wright Millsand the Power Elite. Boston: Beacon Press.

Dye, Thomas 1995 Who's Running America? The ClintonYears. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall.

Field, G. Lowell, and John Higley 1980 Elitism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Hunter, Floyd 1953 Community Power Structure. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.

Jessop, Bob 1990 State Theory: Putting Capitalist States intheir Place. University Park: Penn State University Press.

Keller, Suzanne 1963 Beyond the Ruling Class: StrategicElites in Modern Society. New York: Random House.

Lindbloom, Charles 1977 Politics and Markets. New York: Basic Books.

MacKinnon, Catherine 1989 Toward a Feminist Theory ofthe State. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Mannheim, Karl 1940 Man and Society in an Age ofReconstruction. London: Kegan Paul.

Marger, Martin N. 1987 Elites and Masses: An Introductionto Political Sociology. Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth.

Michels, Robert (1915) 1959 Political Parties. New York: Dover.

Miliband, Ralph 1969 The State in Capitalist Society. New York: Basic Books.

Mills, C. Wright 1956 The Power Elite. New York: Oxford University Press.

Mosca, Gaetano 1939 The Ruling Class. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Pareto, Vilfredo 1935 The Mind and Society. New York: Harcourt Brace.

Parsons, Talcott 1940 "An Analytical Approach to the Theory of Social Stratification." American Journal ofSociology 45:841–862

1951 The Social System. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.

Pateman, Carole 1970 Participation and Democratic Theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Piven, Frances, and Richard Cloward 1977 Poor People'sMovements. New York: Random House.

Prewitt, Kenneth, and Alan Stone 1973 The Ruling Elites. New York: Harper & Row.

Riesman, David 1950 The Lonely Crowd. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.

Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1942 Capitalism, Socialism, andDemocracy. New York: Harper Colophon.

Skocpol, Theda 1985 "Bringing the State Back In: Strategies of Analysis in Current Research." In Peter Evans, Dietrich Reuschemeyer, and Theda Skocopol, eds. Bringing the State Back In. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Truman, David B. 1951 The Governmental Process. New York: Random House.

Tumin, Melvin, 1953 "Some Principles of Stratification: A Critical Analysis." American Sociological Review 18: 387–393.

Useem, Michael 1983 The Inner Circle: Large Corporationsand the Rise of Business Political Activity in the U.S. andthe U.K. New York: Oxford University Press.

Waxman, Chaim I. ed. 1968 The End of Ideology Debate. New York: Clarion.

Weber, Max, (1921) 1968. Economy and Society, vols. Berkeley: University of California Press.


Patrick Akard

More From encyclopedia.com

About this article

Social and Political Elites

Updated About encyclopedia.com content Print Article

You Might Also Like