Time: Physical and Biological Aspects
Time: Physical and Biological Aspects
Insofar as science aims at reconstructing the laws of nature, which describe the temporal development of nature's physical constituents and allow for predicting future events out of data derived from past events, time is a fundamental and crucial notion of empirical sciences. Science, however, does not deal with time itself, but with changes and events in time. Consequently, what really matters in science "is not how we define time, but how we measure it" (Feynman, p. 5-1). As such, time constitutes the realm, rather than the object, of scientific investigation. The nature and character of time must be derived from interpretation of the basic structure of science and its method. And because time does not refer to external objects of investigation, but to the presupposed internal order of physical phenomena, it is closely related to human experience and the human perception of time, which is the sequential, nonspatial order of events, structured by the relation of cause and effect. Unlike space, time as sequential order shows a fundamental asymmetry between the past (fixed in documents, which can be investigated) and the future (still to come and not totally fixed—it can only be predicted). People can remember the past but not the future; people can alter the future, but not the past. The astronomer Arthur S. Eddington (1882–1944) was the first to speak of the "arrow of time," which points from the past to the future, to symbolize this fundamental asymmetry.
The physics of time
The crucial question of the interpretation of time in physics and biology is whether this asymmetry is due to physical laws, or whether it is a subjective illusion due to the human experience of time. The laws of both classical and relativistic physics, as well as the basic equations of quantum physics, are time reversal invariant and provide no scientific ground for an arrow of time. On the other hand, an irreversible directedness of time does turn up in empirical sciences related to different phenomena:
- According to the Second Law of Thermodynamics, disorder (entropy) increases in a closed system from past to future.
- The measurement of quantum events constitutes an irreversible difference between past and future.
- Biological systems and their evolution constitute a historical development from past to future.
- The universe is expanding in time.
Because time and irreversibility seem to have different meanings in different physical theories, and because the notions of causality involved are a matter of dispute as well, a comprehensive and commonly accepted interpretation of time in natural sciences is neither at hand nor in sight. This entry will refer to some aspects of an ongoing discussion.
Newtonian time of classical physics. In his Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Isaac Newton (1642–1727) distinguishes between absolute and relative time: "Absolute, true, and mathematical time . . . flows equably without relation to anything external, and by another name is called duration: relative, apparent, and common time, is some sensible and external (whether accurate or unequable) measure of duration by the means of motion, which is commonly used instead of true time; such as an hour, a day, a month, a year" (p. 6). The notion of absolute time is crucial for Newtonian physics because its First Law of Motion implies that a body on which no forces act moves uniformly in a straight line at constant speed, or it is at rest. Only against the background of absolute time and space can rest and equable translation as free from external influence stand out against those deformations of motion that indicate external forces. Thus, absolute time in Newtonian physics is an a priori presupposition, and it is essential for the frame of reference, against which all forces are determined. Newton himself considered that in reality there might exist no absolutely equable form of motion representing this absolute time: It might not be the time of a particular clock. But still, the assumed flowing of absolute time should not be liable to any change.
However, the laws of classical mechanics, which describe the motions of massive bodies, do not distinguish a direction of absolute time: No feature of the mechanical world would change, if time were reversed. Because the basic differential equations of classical mechanics are time reversal invariant, the future development of any mechanical system is in principle derivable from its past state, and vice versa. Thus, development from past to future and from future to past are physically equivalent.
The arrow of time in thermodynamics. But what people experience in reality are often processes, which appear to be irreversibly "directed," such as the cooling of hot water or the erosion of a rock. Especially inanimate natural systems show a tendency to spontaneously evolve to equilibrium of order, energy, or temperature, where these macroscopic parameters remain approximately stable, and they never leave this state, provided no external intervention takes place. The physics to describe such processes is called thermodynamics. Elaborated in the mid-nineteenth century, classical thermodynamics is based on two laws, the second of which expresses the temporally asymmetric behavior of all isolated (adiabatic) systems, with the universe as the biggest of them, to approach equilibrium in due course of time. The universe thus faces heat death, the equilibrium state in which no energy differences remain and all physical processes come to an end, as its final fate. In order to express this fundamental law, Rudolf Clausius (1822–1888) coined the term entropy (from Greek entrope, turning toward) as a measure of dispersed and irretrievable energy that becomes unavailable for producing work. Clausius further stated that the entropy of the universe strives toward a maximum. Because entropy is at a maximum when the molecules of a system are at the same energy level, entropy can be understood as a measure of disorder. Thus, the Second Law of Thermodynamics implies the increase of disorder in due course of time, ruling out all reverse processes that could create order spontaneously within a closed system.
When James Maxwell (1831–1879) and others developed the kinetic theory of heat and gases, Ludwig Boltzmann (1844–1906) tried to reduce thermodynamics to mechanical laws and interpret the Second Law as only statistical: Systems generally develop toward states of higher entropy because such states are more probable than others. But the discussion about the statistical interpretation of thermodynamics revealed that the time reversal invariance of the mechanical laws cannot model the irreversible phenomena of macroscopic systems striving toward equilibrium. In the light of classical mechanism, the irreversible direction of time from past to future, the arrow of time as indicated by the Second Law of Thermodynamics, seems to rest on no physical ground.
Time in Special and General Theory of Relativity. The direction of time from past to future seemed to become even more illusionary when Albert Einstein's (1879–1955) Theory of Relativity succeeded in overcoming the Newtonian notion of absolute time. In his 1905 Special Theory of Relativity, Einstein stated that the time interval (and the distance) between two events depends on the observer's velocity relative to the events, while the velocity cannot exceed the speed of light.
In Einstein's theory, space and time together constitute the four-dimensional space-time, while each reference frame of an observer divides spacetime differently into a temporal and a spatial component relative to its state of velocity. There is no simultaneity of events and absolute duration of time for every observer, as well as no absolute spatial distance. Still, there is an objective causal connection between events, because one event cannot interact with another instantaneously, but only mediated by forces, whose propagation speed is final and equals or is less than the speed of light. Thus temporal as well as spatial intervals between causally related events cannot become zero, and their causal relation cannot be reversed. Relativistic time still represents the order of causal chains.
Shortly after Einstein's discovery, the Russian mathematician and physicist Hermann Minkowski (1864–1909) united space and time into one four-dimensional continuum, the space-time of the socalled Minkowksi-world: "Henceforth space by itself, and time by itself, are doomed to fade away into mere shadows, and only a kind of union of the two will preserve an independent reality" (Space and Time, p. 75). This view of the physical world, in which no independent time exists, suggests that the world is to be envisioned as a four-dimensional being, rather than a becoming within three-dimensional space. Then, as Einstein himself stated, for a physicist "the distinction between past, present and future is only an illusion, however persistent" (quoted in Davies, 1983, p.128).
Time in quantum theory. In the Schrödingerequation, which is the basic formula of quantum mechanics, time is not an observable, but just a parameter. Although it is time reversal invariant, in its common interpretation, the equation refers to probabilities and only allows for the determination of probabilities for certain states. When a state is measured, the Schrödinger wave-function of an object, which is derived from the Schrödingerequation, "collapses," and a certain value for an observable is provided. Some physicists interpret this as a new notion of irreversible physical time: "The concept of becoming acquires a meaning in physics: The present, which separates the future from the past, is the moment when that which was undetermined becomes determined, and 'becoming' means the same as 'becoming determined'" (Reichenbach, p. 269).
Thus, quantum theory seems to include two concepts of time: time in the form of a classical, reversible parameter of continuous time, in which the realm of probabilities unfolds; and time in the form of the discontinuous interaction between objects, which reduces knowledge of possible states into factual, documented knowledge. Because of fundamental theoretical reasons and because of the very precise empirical data available, a dynamical description of the transition from the probability description to the factual description cannot be modeled within the theory. Thus quantum-measurement seems to establish a fundamental distinction between past and future within physics, with past and future being closely related, but without the possibility of completely deriving the factual future out of the factual past, and vice versa.
Time and biological systems
According to the Second Law of Thermodynamics, flows of energy arise far from equilibrium in order to compensate energy differences and to increase entropy. The Earth, for example, receives a constant flow of energy from the sun and dissipates energy into its cold surroundings. This energy flow establishes a direction of time, which can be identified as the source of the temporality of complex systems, biological systems in particular. Such systems are able to exploit energy flows to locally inverse the increase of entropy and to maintain themselves in a steady state far from equilibrium by functional closure against their environment. They may even develop toward states of increased order and organization, as the contingent and irreversible evolution of life on the planet shows. Biological systems can differentiate, interact, and organize themselves; they can form populations, families, and ecosystems; and, in the case of human beings, they can begin to establish history as the temporal unfolding of rational, self-conscious, and moral social agency.
The cosmological foundation of time
All manifestations of irreversible time can be seen as a consequence of the fact that the universe started off with the Big Bang in a smooth and organized state of low entropy. The interplay of its expansion with the contracting force of gravitation, which agglomerates matter into bodies of high density that start to radiate and disperse their energy into the expanding void, is responsible for the cosmos still being far away from equilibrium. It remains a matter of dispute whether cosmic time will end in a final collapse of the universe, when gravitation will have superseded expansion and reversed it into contraction, or whether expansion will go on forever, until all order and structure of the universe has been dissolved into an ever dispersing radiation field with decaying minimal fluctuations. But the expansion of the universe establishes a cosmic time, which is the origin of the large-scale arrow of time, in whose due course, in a favored niche far away from equilibrium, biological systems could evolve and develop into conscious beings, who start wondering what time is all about.
See also Entropy; Physics, Quantum; Relativity, General Theory of; Relativity, Special Theory of; Space and Time; Thermodynamics, Second
Law of; Time: Religious and Philosophical Aspects
Bibliography
albert, david z. time and chance. cambridge, mass.: harvard university press, 2000.
callender, craig, and edney, ralph. introducing time. cambridge, uk: icon, 2001.
davies, paul c. god and the new physics. new york: simon & schuster, 1983.
davies, paul c. about time: einstein's unfinished revolution. london: viking, 1995.
denbigh, kenneth g. three concepts of time. berlin and new york: springer-verlag, 1981.
eddington, arthur s. the nature of the physical world. cambridge, uk: cambridge university press, 1928.
feynman, richard. the feynman lectures on physics, vol. 1. reading, mass.: addison-wesley, 1963.
friedman, michael. foundations of space-time theories: relativistic physics and philosophy of science. princeton, n.j.: princeton university press, 1983.
hawking, stephen, and penrose, roger. the nature of space and time. princeton, n.j.: princeton university press, 1996.
macey, samuel l. time: a bibliographic guide. new york: garland, 1991.
minkowski, hermann. space and time (1908). in the principle of relativity, ed. albert einstein, et al. new york: dover, 1952.
newton, isaac. the mathematical principles of natural philosophy (1729), trans. andrew motte. facsimile reprint. london: dawson, 1968.
reichenbach, hans. the direction of time. berkeley and los angeles: university of california press, 1956.
turetzky, philip. time. london: routledge, 1998.
dirk evers
More From encyclopedia.com
About this article
Time: Physical and Biological Aspects
You Might Also Like
NEARBY TERMS
Time: Physical and Biological Aspects